Nature, Vol. 329, No.
6140, pp595-598, 15 October 1987
Where science has gone wrongT. Theocharis and M. Psimopoulis In 1968 Sir Peter Medawar wrote: Ask a scientist
what he conceives the scientific method to be, and he will adopt an
expression that is at once solemn and shifty-eyed: solemn because he feels he
ought to declare an opinion; shifty-eyed because he is wondering how to
conceal the fact that he has no opinion to declare 1. The witty style of this passage might amuse the reader. But the
humorous tone only serves to conceal the gravity of the matter. Medawar's remarks were made in the, financially speaking, halcyon
days of the 1960s. The British science budget was then increasing by over 10
per cent every five years in real terms. The growth continued in the 1970s,
though at a lower rate. But a drastic reversal occurred in the 1980s. During
the first five years of this decade, public expenditure on science in Britain
declined by over 10 per cent in real terms, and all the signs indicate that
the cutbacks will continue. But British scientists cannot complain that they
had not been warned. In 1971 Shirley Williams, then a Member of Parliament
and later (1976-1979) Secretary of State for Education and Science, spelled
out an unmistakable warning: For the scientists, the
party is over .... Until fairly recently no one has asked any awkward
questions . . . .Yet there is a growing suspicion about scientists and their
discoveries . . . . It is within this drastically altered climate that the
dramatic decline in expenditure on scientific research in Britain is taking
place. Public spending on science has declined in other countries too. But a
combination of reasons peculiar to Britain has made the situation perhaps the
worst in any advanced industrial state. It is not our intention to discuss here
all these reasons. Rather our objective is to identify and endeavour to
combat what we consider to be the most fundamental, and yet the least
recognized, cause of the present predicament of science, not only in Britain
but throughout the world. In 1986 British scientists reacted to the cutbacks with the launching
of a campaign called Save British Science (SBS). Its stated objectives were: … to communicate to the public, Parliament and Government a proper appreciation of the economic and cultural benefits of scientific and technological research and development, and of the consequent importance to the nation of adequate funding of research by Government and industry. These are also the declared aims 3,4 of the Royal Society (RS). As its
President Sir George Porter says, the RS "is effectively the national
academy of science of the UK and it must therefore assume some special
responsibility for science in this country" 5. Interestingly, British philosophers were quick to emulate the scientists
in "Having lost their
monopoly in the production of knowledge, scientists have also lost their
privileged status in society. Thus the rewards to the creators of science's
now ephemeral and disposable theories are currently being reduced to accord
with their downgraded and devalued work, and with science's diminished
ambitions." launching their own campaign to save British philosophy, for the latter too has had its share of budget cuts 6. In this article we argue that the British scientific and philosophical communities, and in particular the RS, have to their cost neglected one important factor in implementing their policies, and that therefore the present financial crisis is to a considerable extent self-inflicted. On 17 and 22 February 1986 BBC television broadcast, in the highly
regarded Horizon series, a film entitled "Science . . . Fiction?",
and in the issue of 20 February 1986 The
Listener published an article entitled "The Fallacy of
Scientific Objectivity" 7. As is evident from their titles, these were
attacks against objectivity, truth and science. After rehashing the usual
anti-science chestnuts, both the film and the article came to this
conclusion: "The gradual recognition of these arguments may affect the
practice, the funding and the institutions
of science" (our italics). At least in Britain, the repercussions of
these mistaken arguments are already happening. Scientists in other countries
are duly forewarned. We shall refer to these erroneous and harmful ideas as the
epistemological antitheses - the (un)philosophical positions which are
contrary to the traditional and successful theses of natural philosophy.
(Epistemology is the study of the nature, generation and validation of
knowledge.) Articles and programmes attacking the scientific theses and
championing the antitheses are published and broadcast regularly by the
British media. But oddly, the RS, SBS and the other scientific bodies remain
silent and do not deploy their powerful corporate muscle to answer such
attacks against science (and sometimes against the RS itself). As a result,
it appears, the editors of the popular media have come to the conclusion that
the RS has no satisfactory answer. This state of affairs is bad enough. But things are even worse:
perversely, many individual scientists and philosophers seem bent on
questioning and rejecting the true theses, and supporting the antitheses. For
example, most of the participants in the "Science . . . Fiction?"
film were academic scientists. What is more, the RS apparently co-operated in
the making of this programme: a scene in which the RS was explicitly
assailed, was filmed in the RS's own London headquarters. In order to demonstrate the threats that the antitheses pose not only
to science but also to society in general, it is useful to outline briefly
the manner in which these ideas emerged gradually in the twentieth century. In 1919 Sir Karl Popper by his own account 8 had taken a strong dislike to the theories of Marx, Freud and Adler, whose supporters maintained that they were scientific. The difficulty was that Popper could not find any obvious way to refute them conclusively. Having noticed that Einstein's theories made (what seemed to him) falsifiable predictions, Popper resolved all his difficulties simply by declaring: "Irrefutability is not a virtue of a theory (as people often think) but a vice . . . . The criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability" 8. (Example: "The Earth is (approximately) a sphere" is not a scientific statement because it is not falsifiable; whereas "The Earth is a flat disk" is indeed scientific.) Popper also thought that observations arc theory-laden. He phrased it thus: "Sense-data, untheoretical items of observation, simply do not exist. A scientific theory is an organ we develop outside our skin, while an organ is a theory we develop inside our skin" 9. But if observations are
theory-laden, this means that observations are p2, p596 simply theories, and then
how can one theory falsify (never mind verify) another theory? Curiously, the
full implications of this little complication 'were not fully grasped by
Popper, but by Imre Lakatos; not only are scientific theories not verifiable,
they are not falsifiable either – “If a theory is refuted. it is not
necessarily false” 10. (Example: both "the Earth is round" and
"the Earth is flat" are neither verifiable nor falsifiable.) As
David Stove 11 remarked. Lakatos has removed the logical stigma of falsity
from refuted propositions, just as earlier public benefactors had removed the
social stigma of illegitimacy from certain individuals. So back to square one: if verifiability and falsifiability are not
the criteria, then what makes a proposition scientific? It is hard to discern
the answer to this question in Lakatos's writings. But if any answer is
discerned at all, it is one that contradicts flagrantly the motto of the RS:
"I am not bound to swear as any master dictates". This answer is
more obvious in Thomas Kuhn's 12 writings: a proposition is scientific if it
is sanctioned by the scientific establishment. (Example: if the scientific
establishment decrees that "fairies exist", then this would be
scientific indeed.) According to Kuhn, science is not the steady, cumulative acquisition
of knowledge that was portrayed in old-fashioned textbooks. Rather, it is an
endless succession of long peaceful periods which are violently interrupted
by brief intellectual revolutions. During the peaceful period, which Kuhn
calls "normal science", scientists are guided by a set of theories,
standards and methods, which Kuhn collectively designates as a
"paradigm". (Others call it a "world-view".) During a
revolution, the old paradigm is violently overthrown and replaced by a new
one. Vogues
So according to Kuhn, the business of science is not about truth and reality; rather, it is about transient vogues - ephemeral and disposable paradigms. In fact three pages from the end of his book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 12 Kuhn himself drew attention to the fact that up to that point he had not once used the term "truth". And when he used it, it was to dismiss it: "We may have to relinquish the notion that changes of paradigm carry scientists . . . closer and closer to the truth". This passage was quoted approvingly by the author of a review in Science, whose final assessment of Kuhn's book was this: Since Kuhn does not permit truth to be a criterion of scientific theories, he would presumably not claim his own theory to be true. But if causing a revolution is the hallmark of a superior paradigm, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions has been a resounding success". So now that the term "truth" has become a taboo, we know what must take its place: mass popularity and prevailing fashion. Kuhn's view, that a proposition is scientific if it is sanctioned by
the scientific establishment, gives rise to the problematic question: what
exactly makes an establishment "scientific"? This particular
Gordian knot was cut by Paul Feyerabend: any
proposition is scientific - "There
is only one principle that can be defended under all circumstances and in all
stages of human development. It is the principle: Anything goes"
14 (Example: "There are one million fairies in Britain" is as
scientific as "There are two hydrogen atoms in one water
molecule".) In 1979 Science published
a four-page complimentary feature 15 about Feyerabend, the Salvador Dali of
academic philosophy, and currently the worst enemy of science. In this
article Feyerabend was quoted as stating that "normal science is a fairy
tale" and that "equal time should be given to competing avenues of
knowledge such as astrology, acupuncture, and witchcraft". Oddly,
religion was omitted. For according to Feyerabend (and the "Science . .
. Fiction?" film too 7), religion - and everything else - is an equally
valid avenue of knowledge. In fact on one occasion Feyerabend
characteristically put science on a par with "religion, prostitution and
so on" 14. This is a queer theme to pursue, but it is really a serious
matter. For whereas in Britain the hot issue has been the cutbacks in the
science budget, in the United States the most conspicuous impact of the
antitheses has been the alarming growth of religious fundamentalism. All this
and much else notwithstanding, the Science article's assessment of
Feyerabend's monstrous ideas was: "Compared with the stiff and sober
work that is often done in the philosophy of science, Feyerabend's views are
a breath of fresh air" 15 Fortunately, the fallacies of the antitheses have been exposed by
other academic philosophers, and the best debunking known to us was carried
out by David Stove 11. Yet, one or other version of them remains popular with
many philosophers, scientists, the media and the public. The epistemological antitheses - scepticism, agnosticism,
criticismism 11, cynicism, relativism, anarchism, nihilism - are not of
course the invention of the twentieth century. Indeed the agnostic,
nihilistic and anarchistic views of Gorgias, a fifth century BC Greek
sophist, sound refreshingly modern. Aristotle 16 (fourth century BC) reported
that Gorgias taught that "nothing exists: and if anything exists, it is
unknowable; and if it exists and it is knowable, yet it cannot be indicated
to others". Gorgias also argued that "one can persuade anyone of
anything, if one speaks well enough". The correct answer to this typical
sophistry was already known to Aristotle: "One is more likely to win
one's argument, if what one says is true". But it is sadly the case that
those such as Gorgias and Feyerabend can fool a lot of people a lot of the time
with sophistries like "anything goes". But of course in the long
run one thing goes - objective truth. Falsity
For reasons known only to themselves, the advocates of the antitheses
refuse to recognize that their ideas are flagrantly self-refuting - they
negate and destroy themselves. And if a statement entails its own falsity,
then it must be nonsense: the proposition "there is no truth"
contradicts itself, and hence some truths must exist after all. Similarly,
the stricture "nothing is certain, everything is doubtful"' casts
doubt, besides everything else, upon itself, and so some certain and
undoubted things must exist. Likewise, if "anything goes", then
"nothing goes" must go too. To most people this is sufficient refutation of the antitheses. But
instead the sceptics and nihilists persist with doubting anything and
everything with a cocksureness that beats any avowed dogmatist - they are
dogmatical sceptics, and they would question anything except their own
doubts. In the same vein, the epistemological relativists, who uphold the
complete equivalence of all "paradigms", may be aptly termed
absolute relativists. In any event, the spectacle of the supporters of the antitheses appealing to the very standards which they are bent on attacking is reassuring to those who uphold these standards. For example, those who claim to have refuted inductive reasoning have done so by employing inductive reasoning itself, as follows: from the true fact that many examples of inductive inference have indeed been shown to be invalid, these people inferred (inductively!) that all examples of inductive inference will be shown to be invalid. On the subject of how to
teach these weird modern ideas, we turn to the currently popular book What Is This Thing Called Science? 17 by
Alan Chalmers. It was first published in 1976 as a textbook for introductory
university courses in the philosophy of science. Its popularity has been so
great that it has been translated into many languages, and a new edition was
published in 1982. The heading of the last section of the last chapter of the
1982 edition is "Why Bother?", and the answer is revealing:
"Why bother to carry out investigations of the kind to be found in the
foregoing pages? The importance of the question becomes highlighted once it is
admitted that' philosophy or methodology- of science is of no help to
scientists". After 168 pages packed with subtle concepts, sophisticated
ideas and complex arguments, and after a gruelling academic session of
(apparently futile) study, this must surely come as a rude p3, p597 shock to the serious
student of science. But the student cannot complain. For Chalmers himself
with commendable frankness notified the reader of the book from the outset,
in the Introduction, what to expect from studying it: "We start off
confused and end up confused on it higher level". But come to think of it, once it is accepted, as done in this book, that the business of science is not about the discovery of truth and reality, then its conclusion that the methodology of science is of no help to scientists sounds eminently plausible: epistemological anarchism is a method, and nihilism is an (un)philosophical stance - and they do not require any special learning. Anyhow, Chalmers's answer tit the hot question "Why Bother:'", is that "as there is no timeless and universal conception of science or scientific method", the most important function of his book is to combat
what might he called the ideology of
science as it functions in our society. This ideology involves the
use of the dubious concept of science and the equally dubious concept of
truth that is often associated with it, usually in the defence of
conservative positions [italics in original]. While agreeing that genuine science cannot rationally defend any subjective ideological opinion, conservative or not, to dismiss science itself its just another ideology, and to allege that only passionate ideologues (but not dispassionate scientists) may benefit from the philosophy and methodology of science, is to talk nonsense. Yet sadly this is what mane students of science, technology and medicine are taught in universities, and as a result these preposterous and dangerous ideas are becoming widespread within the scientific community. It is an objective of this article to refute these ideas, and argue that the correct epistemology is indispensable in any serious and responsible scientific work. For what is really at stake is nothing less than the future progress of our civilization. One may wonder how many universities in the world give their science
students compulsory formal courses of lectures on the rigours of the
scientific method. As for those universities which provide their students
with an optional course on the current trends in the philosophy of science,
are their governing bodies aware of the fact that many teachers of these
courses are bent on sabotaging the scientific method? Methodology
The hapless student is inevitably left to his or her own devices to
pick up casually and randomly, from here and there, unorganized hits of tile
scientific method, as well its bits of unscientific
methods. And when the student becomes the professional researcher, lacking
proper tuition and training, he or she will grope haphazardly in the dark,
follow expensive blind alleys and have recourse to such (unreliable) things
as random guess, arbitrary conjecture, subjective hunch, casual intuition,
raw instinct, crude imagination, pure chance, lucky accident and unplanned
trial - and invariable error. Can this be an adequate methodology by means of
which to make new discoveries and beneficial applications? Of course not, yet
this is the entire methodology that the exponents of tile antitheses actually
recommend to professional researchers. In the light of this evidence, Medawar's statement 1 does not seem
surprising at all. In that passage Medawar suggested that the scientist
"has no opinion" as to "what he conceives the scientific
method to be". This might not be true of every scientist, but it appears
to be true of quite a few. What is more, there has never been any attempt to
rectify this worrying situation because, oddly and sadly, it was never seen
as the anomalous circumstance that it indubitably is, and as the grave
problem that it inevitably became. Even though the endorsement of the antitheses saves one from the
painstaking effort of discovering new truths, such conduct has some
unfortunate drawbacks: the antitheses pose at least three different kinds of
potential threats or actual dangers not only to science as such, but also to
society in general. In summary, these risks are: (i) Intellectual bankruptcy
entails financial bankruptcy. (ii) Epistemological anarchism entails social
anarchism. (iii) Epistemological relativism, criticismism 11 and nihilism
entail scientific chaos, confusion and stagnation. Danger (i). The first harmful
repercussion of the antitheses, namely the cutback in the science budget, is
already happening. The logical steps leading from the antitheses to the
inescapable conclusion that the funding of science should be cut are not
usually spelled out in detail. We spell them out now. In the golden age of science, it was believed that the verified
theories of science were true and everlasting. But with the increasing
acceptance of the antitheses, these exalted old ambitions of science are seen
as bogus. According to epistemological relativism, science should no longer
claim superiority for its method and the knowledge that it produces.
Moreover, in the capitalist system of economy, a scientific theory is a
commodity like any other, and it must obey the laws of this system.
Scientific theories are now considered to he temporary and dispensable.
Furthermore, by denying truth and reality, the antitheses reduce science to a
pointless, if entertaining, game; a meaningless, if exacting, exercise; and a
destinationless, if enjoyable, journey. The aim of the game is just to play:
the object of the exercise is merely to keep one busy: and the purpose of the
journey is but aimless wandering. Having lost their monopoly in the production of knowledge, scientists have also lost their privileged status in society. Thus the rewards to the creators of science's now ephemeral and disposable theories are currently being reduced to accord with their downgraded and devalued work, and with science's diminished ambitions. It is the duty of those who want to save science, both intellectually and financially, to refute the antitheses, and to reassure their paymasters and p4, p598 the public that the genuine
theories of science are of permanent value, and that scientific research does
have a concrete and positive and useful aim - to discover the truth and
establish reality. It is only on true knowledge that the socially beneficial and
economically profitable medical and technological applications can be firmly
grounded - knowledge normally discovered by means of the valid and judicious
application of the scientific method. Now the hard fact is that most
governments, being the political institutions that they are, provide public
funds for research on the condition that the findings of this research will,
sooner rather than later, have economic returns. For example, the British
government told Parliament in 1986 18that it (the government) is more likely to be persuaded of the value of increasing public investment in science, if the scientific community, and the users of its products, can point to increasing economic and social benefits, and in particular to prospects for increased national wealth. Actually the ultimate reason cited by Shirley Williams in 1971 for the "dramatic decline in expenditure on scientific research in Britain", was that the "expected outcome" of the previously lavish spending, namely "an increase in gross national product", in fact "never happened". In the wake of the rejection of scientific truth by so many
researchers, and their candid admission that they do not really know what the
scientific method is, the unpalatable fact pointed out by Williams is hardly
surprising. If anything is surprising, it is the curious fact that some of
the manufacturers of deficient, perishable and basically useless products -
the short-lived, disposable and basically untrue theories - should complain
that the selling price of their inferior product is dwindling. It is therefore clear that the usual plea that greater funding of
science results in proportionally greater wealth is woefully inadequate.
Apart from increased funding, another requirement is increased care in the
correct and sagacious application of the scientific method. Thus before
laying all the blame at the doors of government and industry, the scientific
community should put its own house in order. It is not enough for scientists to assert vaguely that basic research
will (just possibly) lead to new discoveries and profitable applications.
Those scientists who want to uphold the intellectual integrity of their
profession, and who are interested in selling their skills in the
marketplace, owe it to their paymasters to explain adequately how they
propose to make new and fruitful discoveries, instead of trying to conceal
the embarrassing fact that they do not really know what the scientific method
is. Danger (ii). A second danger could
have an impact both broader and more disastrous than the first. This lies in
the fact that epistemological cynicism and anarchism entail social, political
and every other kind of anarchism and disorder. For it is not only in formal
science that the issue of objective truth arises - it arises in every
department of life. Both truths - ordinary and scientific - are of the same
character in that they are both established by, either natural or artificial,
either simple or By denying truth and reality science is reduced to a pointless, if entertaining, game; a meaningless, if exacting, exercise; and a destinationless, if enjoyable, journey. sophisticated, observations. In fact the only meaningful definition of truth is by way of the objectivity of theory-free and context-transcendent observation. If one kind of truth is denied, the other will have to go too. Now if the notion of objective truth established by observational evidence is disregarded, one is left in a chaos of arbitrary and conflicting opinions, opinions which are equally well- or ill-founded. For from the, false premise that all observation is theory-dependent, all routes lead inexorably to "anything goes". Danger (iii). A third
danger springs from the fact that the antitheses are by nature obscurantist and
they inevitably stifle progress. In the jungle of epistemological anarchism
and criticismism11, every single bit of painstakingly proven knowledge is
frivolously questioned and cynically scoffed at. In the consequent
intellectual chaos there results a thick fog of confusion which completely
obscures every possible route to further discoveries, and in this way the
quest to enlarge knowledge is effectively paralysed. Moreover, if one believes that there exists no objective truth, or
even if one has doubts as to its existence, one then has no motivation, nor
even inclination, to try to discover it. It is therefore highly unlikely that
such a person would make any new discoveries (funding agencies take note).
Furthermore, scepticism and nihilism were not threats only in the remote
past; nor do they now constitute a risk of only academic interest. There
seems to be evidence 19, 20 indicating that they may be impairing scientific
progress at this moment. Natural philosophy has had enemies throughout its 2,600 or so years
of recorded history. But the present era is unique in that it is the first
civilized society in which an effective anti-science movement flourishes
contemporaneously with the unprecedently magnificent technological and
medical applications of modern science. This is a curious paradox which cries
out for clarification. The explanation of this sad situation is, of course,
the large number of errors regarding the nature, scope, method, powers and
limitations of science. It is not the objective of this article to correct all the errors which plague science and philosophy today, or to present the detailed solutions to all of the vexed problems of epistemology. For this is a colossal task, a task however that scientists are obliged to undertake themselves. The purpose of this article is merely to show that an acute problem exists, and to indicate broadly how it can be solved. The problem is that although the epistemological antitheses are demonstrably untenable, inherently obscurantist and positively dangerous, they have become alarmingly popular with the public, and even worse, with the communities of professional philosophers and scientists. In barest outline, the solution of the problem is that science and philosophy will be saved - in both the intellectual and the financial sense - when the practitioners of these disciplines stop running down their own professions and start pleading the cause of science and philosophy correctly. This should be best done, first by thoroughly refuting the erroneous and harmful antitheses; secondly by putting forth adequate definitions of such fundamental concepts as objectivity, truth, rationality and the scientific method; and thirdly by putting the latter judiciously into fruitful practice. Only then will the expounding of the positive virtues of science and philosophy carry conviction. I. Medawar. P.B. Induction and Intuition in Scientific Thought 11
(Methuen, London. 1969). 2. Williams, S. The Times 15 (27 February 1971). 3. The Public Understanding of Science (The
Royal Society. London. 1985). 4. The Royal Society Corporate Plat: A Strategy for
the Royal Socierv 1986-1996
(The Royal Society. London, 1996). 5. Porter. G. Supplement to Royal Society News 3,
i-vi (1986). 6.
Alexander, P. et al. Analysis 46, 161 (1986). 7. Lawson. H. The Listener 115, 12-13 (261 February
1986). H. Popper, K.R. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of
Scientific Knowledge 4th edn 33-37 (Routledge & Kegan Paul.
London, 1972). 9. Popper, K.R. in Problems in the Philosophy of Science
(eds Lakatos. 1. & Musgrave, A.) 163-164 (North Holland. Amsterdam.
1968). 10. Lakatos, 1. in The Problem of Inductive Logic (ed. Lakatos, 1.) 397 (North Holland.
Amsterdam. 1968). 11. I. Stove. D.C. Popper
and After: Four Modern Irrationalists
16 (Pergamon, Oxford, 1982). 12. Kuhn. T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2nd
edn (University of Chicago Press.
Chicago, 1970). 13. Wade. N. Science 197, 143-145 (1977). 14. Feyerabend, P. Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theorv of
Knowledge 28 (New Left Books. London. 1975). 15. Broad, W.J. Science 206, 534-537(1979). 16. Ross. W.D. led.) The Works of Aristotle Volume Vl Opuscula 979a 11- 980h 21 (Clarendon. Oxford. 1913). 17. Chalmers. A.F. What Is This Thing Called Science? An Assessment of
the Nature and the States of science and its Methods 1st edn
(University of Oueensland Press. St Lucia. 1976); 2nd edn (Open University
Press. Milton Keynes. 1982). 18. The Future of the Science Budget: The Government's Response
to the Report from the Education, Science & Arts Committee Session
1984-1985 (Command 9849. HMSO. London, 1986). 19. Sharp Cook. C. Am. J. Phys. 48, 175-176 (1980). 20. Psimopoulos, M. &
Theocharis. T.
Am. J. Phys. 54, 969 (1986). T. Theocharis and M.
Psimopoulos are in the Department of Physics, Imperial College of Science and
Technology, London SW7 2AZ, UK. |
“In many fields there are certain things in vogue at a
given time. Nearly everything published in high energy physics, for example,
is bunk. It has nothing to do with reality – it’s a whole castle of cards.
Yet you are on safe ground if you write a paper according to the currently
accepted style. You will be published, especially if you make some curves and
graphs and make it appear that you did some calculations. The fact that it is
all a house of cards with very little reality to begin with somehow gets
ignored.” – Dr. Lynn Trainor, professor of Physics at the University of
Toronto, in Pensee, May 1972,
vol 2 No. 2, p44. |